Quaid-e-Azam law College

Always bear in mind that your own resolution to succeed is more important than any one thing.

Quaid-e-Azam law College

Identify your problems but give your power and energy to solutions.

Quaid-e-Azam Law college

The only true wisdom is knowing that you know nothing.

Quaid-e-Azam law College

Things work out best for those who make the best of how things work out

Quaid-e-Azam law College

If u don't like any rule,just follow it, reach the top and change the rule........ .

Wednesday, 20 March 2013

Alternate Dispute Resolution


THE DOCTRINE OF “ALTERNATIVE REMEDY” WITH REFERENCE TO WRIT JURISDICTION UNDER THE CONSTITUTION OFPAKISTAN, 1973
Abstract
The present paper would explore the legal principles with reference to the doctrine of alternate remedy in relation with writ jurisdiction of High Courts under the constitution of the Islamic Republic of Pakistan,1973. Inthe light of relevant case law, the scope of the doctrine has been discussed in detail. The doctrine has been established not to deprive a person from justice but to give him a chance to exhaust the ordinary remedies. But this is not a static principle; it has its exceptions too.
Introduction:
The basic and main purpose of framing the law is to maintain justice. If a principle of law does not serve this purpose, it would cause the system failure. It is necessary to maintain balance while applying a principle of law to a certain state of facts, which would lead to upheld the justice. One of the reasons for introducing the doctrine of alternate remedy is to avoid/reduce the number of petitions to be filed directly in the High Courts. Secondly, if a person comes in the High Court without exhausting a remedy available at a lower forum, the purpose of establishing that forum would also be defeated which is against the principle of justice. Thus, it is a matter which requires extra care so that the rights of the individuals must be protected at any cost.
Meaning:
Alternate remedy as it has been held in Rizwan Ullah v. Registrar/President, Cooperative Societies, N.W.F.P. Peshawar and three others, means a remedy, which is adequate, efficacious, expeditious, inexpensive, speedy, prompt, appropriate, exclusive, convenient, beneficial and effective.However, the test of aforesaid connotation of alternate remedy depends upon the relevant facts and law in each case.[1]
Before going onward, the distinction between alternative remedy and adequate remedy must be kept in mind. Both must not be considered the same. When a constitutional petition is filed in the High Court or Supreme Court, the first question which may arise is that whether an alternative remedy is available with reference to the said case or not. If the answer is “No”, the court may proceed and decide the petition. But if the answer is “Yes”, then the second question would arise and that is whether the available alternative remedy is adequate or not. The answer to this question is answered by the Court itself. If the answer to this question is “No”, the Court may proceed further otherwise the Court may refuse the relief.
The first case whereby the concept of alternate remedy has been discussed by the superior courts of Pakistanis the case of Mehboob Ali Malik[2] This case was heard by a Full Bench of five Judges, and the judgment was delivered by Mr. Justice Manzur Qadir. In regard to the principles, governing the grant of relief in cases where alternate remedy was available, criterion was laid down in paragraph 13 of the judgment appearing at page 581.
It provides that if the relief available through the alternative remedy, in its nature or extent is not what is necessary to give the requisite relief, the alternative remedy is not an adequate remedy.[3]
It further provides that if the relief available is equal to what is necessary to give the requisite relief, the adequacy of the alternative remedy must further be judged with reference to a comparison of the speed, expense or convenience of obtaining that relief through the alternative remedy.[4]
Alternate Remedy when bars Writ Jurisdiction:
The Constitution of Pakistan 1973 provides that the writ jurisdiction can be invoked if alternate remedy is not available to the aggrieved party under the relevant law.[5] It can be exercised only on proof of non-availability of alternate remedy. It is, therefore, clear that if an alternate and adequate remedy is available under the relevant law, the jurisdiction as provided under section 199 cannot be invoked.[6]However, in the absence of availability of alternate and adequate remedy the constitutional jurisdiction of Superior Courts may be called upon through the writ petition.[7]
Sometime, an alternate remedy is available but the petition is accepted. At another time, alternate remedy is not available but the petition is not accepted. It is only because of the circumstances of each case. Generally, when an alternate and adequate remedy is available to a person, the High Court does not interfere with the matter. In The Tariq Transport Company Lahorev. The  Sargodha‑Bhera Bus Service, Sargodha, etc.[8] the Supreme Court observed:
“Where a statute creates a right and also provides a machinery for the enforcement of that right, the party complaining of a breach of the statute must first avail himself of the remedy provided by the statute for such breach before he applies for a writ or an order in the nature of a writ.”
In the same case, it was further observed:
“It is wrong on principle to entertain petitions for writs, except in very exceptional circumstances, when the law provides a remedy by appeal to another Tribunal fully competent to award the requisite relief. Any indulgence to the contrary is calculated to create distrust in statutory tribunals of competent jurisdiction and to cast an undeserved reflection on their honesty and competency and thus to defeat the legislative intent.”
The extra-ordinary constitutional writ jurisdiction is entirely discretionary which cannot be exercised in an ordinary course and it must be exercised with great care. It cannot be exercised for “deciding the disputed facts and thwart the procedural law”.[9]
If the remedy sought for, is in substance a remedy, which is available under the ordinary law, then a suit should be the appropriate remedy instead of filing a writ petition, because the remedy provided by the constitution is not intended to be a substitute for the ordinary forms of legal action. However, where this is not the case, the remedy by way of a suit can hardly be considered as an alternate adequate remedy. In such a case, the writ petition may be competent.
The purpose of writ jurisdiction is not to create a competing remedy. It is an additional remedy in the absence of an alternate adequate remedy subject to the satisfaction of the higher court.[10] If the alternate adequate remedy has not been exhausted or if a case requires detailed inquiry, the writ petition may not be allowed.[11] Nevertheless, to exclude the constitutional writ jurisdiction the alternate remedy should be meaningful, effective and adequate otherwise, it would delay the proceedings and it would be a useless exercise, which is equal to denial of justice (justice delayed, justice denied).[12]
If a statute creates a right and provides a remedy in shape of a machinery for enforcement of that right, the party (complaining of breach of the statute) should avail that remedy before invoking writ jurisdiction.[13] For example, in case of a dispute relating to private contract the proper course would be arbitration or institution of suit and not the writ petition.[14] The existence of another remedy does not affect the jurisdiction of the court to issue a writ. It is a thing to be taken into consideration while granting writs and if such remedy is not exhausted, it will be a sound exercise of discretion to refuse to interfere through a constitutional petition unless there are good grounds.[15]
As a rule, a higher court using its discretion may refuse an order of mandamus if an alternative specific remedy at law, which is not less convenient, beneficial, effective or adequate, and such remedy includes an appeal to an appellate tribunal.[16]
In A.V. Venkateswaran, Collector of Customs, Bombay v. Ramchand Sobhraj Wadhwani & another, it has held that even where a party has approached the alternative forum, a straight jacket formula cannot be formulated to decide that whether the Court should entertain a writ petition or not. The Court may examine the facts and circumstances of the case and decide as to whether it was to entertain the petition or not. However, where the petitioner has already approached the alternative forum for appropriate relief, it is not appropriate that the writ petition should be entertained. The rule is based on public policy and the motivating factor is that of existence of the parallel jurisdiction in another Court.[17]
Alternate Remedy when does not bar Writ Jurisdiction:
The rule that a higher court may not entertain a writ petition if any other appropriate remedy is yet available, is not a rule of law barring jurisdiction but a rule by which the court regulates its jurisdiction.[18] Hence, the adequacy of the remedy is not considered as a rule of law and it is dependent on certain factors like discretion of the court, the circumstances, etc.
In the following cases an alternate remedy does not bar the writ jurisdiction:
(i)         Violation of fundamental rights 
The writ jurisdiction cannot be refused on the ground that alternative remedy is available if there is violation of fundamental rights.[19] But if a person invokes jurisdiction of the High Court for any other purpose, the court may refuse the relief in its discretion.[20]
(ii)        Order malafide or unjust, etc.
Even if the remedy is available, the court will decide the adequacy of the alternate remedy. It has been held that the writ jurisdiction will be available in the following cases even if alternate remedy is available:
(i)                  Orders passed arbitrarily[21]
(ii)                Orders passed without lawful authority[22];
(iii)               Orders based on Malafide[23]; and
(iv)              Perverse, unjust and oppressive orders[24].
It is obvious that no inflexible rules can be laid down for the exercise of discretion in this regard. The broad policy behind the doctrine is that the writ jurisdiction is not meant to short-circuit or circumvent statutory procedures. It is only where statutory remedies are entirely ill-suited to meet the demands of extraordinary situations. However, even then the Court must have good and sufficient reasons to bypass the alternative remedy provided by the statute.[25]
(iii)       Alternative remedy inadequate or illusory, etc.
If the alternative remedy is either inadequate,[26] less convenient[27], illusory,[28] meaningless,[29] time consuming,[30] or involves delay,[31] or was lost for no fault of the person,[32] the High Court may grant relief. In Digital World Pakistan (Pvt.) Ltd. through Chief Executive v. Samsung Gulf Electronics FZE through Managing Director/Chief Executive Officer and another, damages were also held as inadequate remedy.[33] In Mian Ayaz Anwar v. Federation of Pakistan through Secretary Interior and 3 others, the remedy of review was also considered as inadequate.[34]
(iv)       Lack or abuse of jurisdiction
In a case where the order has been passed without jurisdiction or is unlawful, it cannot bar the filing of writ petition under Article 199 of the Constitution.[35]
Generally, the High Court, in cases of lack or abuse of jurisdiction, would not hesitate in entertaining constitutional petition although an alternate remedy is available.[36]The same principle would apply in a case of excess of jurisdiction.[37]
An aggrieved party can invoke the constitutional writ jurisdiction where the impugned action is completely without jurisdiction, mala fide, unlawful and passed in disregard of the law and principles of natural justice. It is not necessary to avail alternate remedy in such matters.[38]
(v)        Question of law involved
Where decision of the petition depends upon the resolution of a question of law or interpretation of a law, a writ petition would be maintainable even if the alternate remedy has not been availed.[39]
(vi)       Illegitimate order
In Vincent and others v. Karachi Development Authority and others[40]it was held thatthe mere fact that the right of appeal has been provided under the relevant law, cannot divest jurisdiction of the High Court to entertain a constitutional petition if the circumstances requires so. In this case, the premises in occupation of petitioners was declared to be dangerous on the report of inspection committee without notice to petitioners. The alternate remedy was to file an appeal which could prolong the matter. Thus, it was not proper to dismiss the case.
“Where alternate remedy was not equally efficacious or speedily or where impugned order, as on face of it, is patently, illegal and without lawful authority or suffers from such legal infirmities which are apparent on the face of the record, the court may, in spite the existence of alternate remedy, exercise its jurisdiction under Art.199 of the Constitution.”[41]
In error cases, if the error is apparent on the record, the writ petition may be admitted. For example, a family judge passing an order to evict a tenant.
(vii)      Violation of principles of natural justice
When the constitutionality of an act is challenged or the case involves violation of principles of natural justice, the writ petition may be admitted.[42]
(viii)     Violation of Legal Principles
It was held in a number of cases that where—
(i)                  an order, act or omission is erroneous, autocratic, capricious,[43] or
(ii)                there is total lack of jurisdiction,[44] or
(iii)               a mandatory provision is ignored, or
(iv)              available material evidence is ignored, or
(v)                an action is arbitrary, or
(vi)              an order is tainted with illegality, etc.
(vii)             an order is wholly without authority[45]
the writ petition may be allowed.
(xi)       Mere availability of alternative forum
In M/S. S.J.S. Business Enterprises Ltd. v. State of Bihar (2004 Supp 2 SC 601), the Court has held that mere availability of alternative forum for appropriate relief does not impinge upon the jurisdiction of the High Court to deal with the matter.
It is, thus, clear from the above discussion that in appropriate cases, constitutional jurisdiction can be exercised by High Court even where alternate remedy was available.
Well Recognized Adequate Alternate

This message has been truncated



Tuesday, 19 March 2013

Imprison Reform


New penology and modern prison:
The utility of prison as an institution for rehabilitation of offenders and preparing them for normal life has always been a controversial issue .stressing on the needs for retaining the institutions of prison Dr,verma observed that ‘A prison symbolizes evil and therefore evil doers find themselves in perfect harmony inside the house of evils”. this assertion however seems to be an over simplification of facts as this does not hold good for all categories of criminals . There are a quite large number of offender who are otherwise well behaved and are persons of respectable class of society but they fall a prey to criminality on account of momentary impulsiveness, provocation or due to situational circumstances there is yet another class of prisoners who are otherwise innocent but have to bear the rigors of prison life due miscarriage of justice. Obviously such person’s find it difficult adjusts themselves to the prison surroundings and finds life inside the prison most pain full and disgusting  .
The real purpose of sending criminals to prison is to transform them in to honest , law obliating citizens by inculcating in them  a distaste for crime and criminality . but in actual practice prison authorities try to bring out the formation inmates  by use of force and compulsive methods consequently change in the inmates  is momentry and lasts only till the period they are in prison and as soon as they are released they return to the criminal world .it is for this reason that the modern trend is to lay greater emphasis on psychiatric condition of the prisoners so that they can be rehabilitated to normal life in the community . the objective can successfully achived through the techniques of and probation Parole .the sincerity , devotion and tect fullness of the prison officials also helps conciderably in the process of offender’s rehabilitation .
PRISON DICIPLINE
The problem of prison discipline has always been engaging the attention of penologists throughout the world. The main objective of prisonisation is undoubtedly negative insofar as it aims at generating a feeling of dislike for prison among the members of society, the object being to dissuade people from doing acts which may land them in to prison. Expressing his view about prison, DONALD TAFT commented that “prison is deliberately so planed as to provide unpleasant compulsory isolation from general society”. Prison according to him characterizes rigid discipline, provision of bare necessities, sticks security arrangements and monotonous routine life. Life inside the prison necessarily pre-supposes certain restriction on the liberty of inmates against their free will. This consciousness of subjection to compulsive forces for the state thorough the agency of prison often leads to scuffle between prison officials and the inmates. The custody of prisoners would therefore insure their safity and also minimize the chance of conflict with prison administrators.
Another problem often faces by the prison authorities are to guard against the possibility of prison –riot which is essentially an outcome of the combined venture of inmates. Today the difference between the prison life and free life is reduced to such an extent that even the prisoners have become conscious of their rights and obligation of prison authorities toward the. Their free intermingling with the outside world provides them opportunities to unite and rise a common front against the prison administrators and slightest provocation in sufficient to stimulate unrest. 
SELF GOVERNAMENT IN PRISON
Experiments of self government in prisons have recently been carried out in America and elsewhere. The under laying purpose is to ensure complete freedom to prisoners from external control .under this system the inmates are to elect some off their colleagues as their representative and the entire prison management is run by this elected body of inmates. With this control they look the interests and welfare of their fellow prisons. The self government of prisoners in Osborne(USA) jail indicated that the system proved quite successful and the nimber of escapes were reduced to negligible. The inmate generally behaved well and never tried to misuse the liberty extended to them. The system will not be successful in Pakistan as the condition of our jails is unsatisfactory due to lack of general moral discipline among the criminals who are often illiterate persons form the lower strata of society. It is for this reason that in Pakistan we a system of partial self government in our prisons .prisoners with good reason record are attached to the work with wardens and guards of the institution and thus act as a common link between prison authorities and inmates.  They are extended certain facilities and even allowed to move out of prison occasionally during the course their work. This proves helpful in many ways. It develops a sense of duty, honestly trust and loyalty among prisoners, and secondly it has a psychological effect on other inmates as they are convicted that a disciplined behavior in prison would entail some facilities and deduction in their term of sentence like their fellow prisoners.
PRISON LABOUR
Utilization of prisoners in productive work has been accepted as one of the best method about rehabilitation of offenders. Work is the best alternative for channelizing the potential of prisoners for a useful purpose. It will also be helpful for their physical and mental fitness. It will infuse self confidence among them and they can think of returning to the society as law abiding citizens. The biggest advantage of putting inmates to work can be utilized for supporting their family and dependents. In short work would be beneficial to inmates and at the same time remunerative to the state. The system of parole and probation and other treatment methods have helped considerably in the rehabilitation of prisoners.
The Prison community
Talking about the prison community Prof: Sutherland Observed that “an offender entering a prison for the first time is introduced to the culture in such the same way as a child is introduced to the ways of having with his elders”. According to him the general process by which a child is taught the behaviors of this group is called “socialization” and the compare able process among inmates is name d “Prisonization”. Every new prisoner has to learn the technical rules of the prison in which he Is lodged. Gradually he adopts him self to the condition of prison life .
PROCESS OF INDIVIDUALIZED METHOD IN PRISON
Despite modern techniques of treating the offenders through the process of individualized method in prison there are certain problems that still remain unresolved. The four most difficulties arises in treating recidivists or habitual offenders who do not respond favorably to any of the reformative methods of treatment. They accept prisonization as a normal way of life and criminality as a regular profession.
When recidivists are placed in the correction institution they treat it as a place comfort. Do the treatment methods hardly serve any useful purpose in the case recidivists? Therefore such criminals have got to be confined to for walls of the prison and made to live strictly regulated life. Harden criminals and recidivists are an unnecessary Burdon on the state but they have to tolerated at any rate for the sake of respect for human life and social security. Commenting on the policies to in followed in the cease of recidivists .SIR LIONEL FOX observed “certain people are worth less form social standpoint and are in fact physical mentally an morally a burden to society and their exist no rational reason to provide care for them”.
It should not be forgotten that crimes are essentially conditioned by social, economic and political situations of a particular place. The advancement of knowledge, technology and citizens has brought about radical changes in our social structure, economy, political strategy and thinking. Consequently many new crimes which were hitherto unknown have sprung up, for example the offences of fraud, embezzlement, forgery , theft of auto mobiles ,gang style crime, terrorist activities, tax erosion, infringement of copy right, trademarks and patents and many other. Corrupt practices are relatively of a recent origin. Many old crimes are now repeated with new techniques and methods and which minimal chances of detection. The problem of increase in population, economic depression and criminalization of politics has also contributed to stimulate crime rate .it erroneous to think that rise in criminality is exclusively due to the failure of our penal policies. Far from being so it is infect and indication that we have yet to enlarge the scope of our penal programe to suit the needs of modern times.
The general policy which seems expedient in present context is the institutionalized treatment with provisions of minimum security for adults and greater security for juveniles. The sole contention behind the entire scheme should be to preserve respect for human life at any cost. The ultimate object of prison institution should be to reform the offender rather than to torture and antagonize him. The prison should be moral hospitals or place of reeducation but they should not be so comfortable as to be attractive. An ideal prison must provide for adequate work, vocational training, and basic education, medical and recreational facilities for inmates. The prison management should be made functional, effective and goal-oriented so as to prove itself as an efficient agency of the criminal justice administration.

Modern prisons

It need not be stressed that efforts for rehabilitation of an offender begins from the time he enters the prison. A comprehensive prison programme is therefore essential to cater the needs of different categories of inmates. The prison life should be so regulated that the prisoner is able to overcome all his psychological strains and adopt himself as a law abiding citizen after his release from jail. it is always preferable to place the released prisoners under the supervision and guidance of a probation officer for his aftercare and rehabilitation in the free community. Welfare officers appointed in prisons can also play an important role in providing adequate counseling, legal help and financial assistance to the prisoners at the time of their release so that they are properly rehabilitated in society.
The role of prisons has radically changed over the years and theyt are no longer regarded as mere custodial institutions instead they have now acquired a new dimension as treatment and training centers for those who fall foul with law.

JURISPRUDENCE

Jurisprudence

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Jump to: navigation, search
Philosophers of law ask "what is law?" and "what should it be?"
Jurisprudence is the study and theory of law. Scholars of jurisprudence, or legal theorists (including legal philosophers and social theorists of law), hope to obtain a deeper understanding of the nature of law, of legal reasoning, legal systems and of legal institutions. Modern jurisprudence began in the 18th century and was focused on the first principles of the natural law, civil law, and the law of nations.[1] General jurisprudence can be broken into categories both by the type of question scholars seek to answer and by the theories of jurisprudence, or schools of thought, regarding how those questions are best answered. Contemporary philosophy of law, which deals with general jurisprudence, addresses problems in two rough groups:[2]
  • (1.) Problems internal to law and legal systems as such.
  • (2.) Problems of law as a particular social institution as it relates to the larger political and social situation in which it exists.
Answers to these questions come from four primary schools of thought in general jurisprudence:[2]
  • Natural law is the idea that there are rational objective limits to the power of legislative rulers. The foundations of law are accessible through human reason and it is from these laws of nature that human-created laws gain whatever force they have.[2]
  • Legal positivism, by contrast to natural law, holds that there is no necessary connection between law and morality and that the force of law comes from some basic social facts. Legal positivists differ on what those facts are.[3]
  • Legal realism is a third theory of jurisprudence which argues that the real world practice of law is what determines what law is; the law has the force that it does because of what legislators, judges, and executives do with it. Similar approaches have been developed in many different ways in sociology of law.
  • Critical legal studies is a younger theory of jurisprudence that has developed since the 1970s. It is primarily a negative thesis that holds that the law is largely contradictory, and can be best analyzed as an expression of the policy goals of the dominant social group.[4]
Also of note is the work of the contemporary Philosopher of Law Ronald Dworkin who has advocated a constructivist theory of jurisprudence that can be characterized as a middle path between natural law theories and positivist theories of general jurisprudence.[5]
The English term is based on the Latin word jurisprudentia: juris is the genitive form of jus meaning "law", and prudentia means "prudence" (also: discretion, foresight, forethought, circumspection; refers to the exercise of good judgment, common sense, and even caution, especially in the conduct of practical matters). The word is first attested in English in 1628,[6] at a time when the word prudence had the now obsolete meaning of "knowledge of or skill in a matter". The word may have come via the French jurisprudence, which is attested earlier.

History of jurisprudence

The Central Criminal Court of England and Wales at the Old Bailey
Jurisprudence already had this meaning in Ancient Rome even if at its origins the discipline was a (periti) in the jus of mos maiorum (traditional law), a body of oral laws and customs verbally transmitted "by father to son". Praetors established a workable body of laws by judging whether or not singular cases were capable of being prosecuted either by the edicta, the annual pronunciation of prosecutable offense, or in extraordinary situations, additions made to the edicta. An iudex then would judge a remedy according to the facts of the case.
Their sentences were supposed to be simple interpretations of the traditional customs, but effectively it was an activity that, apart from formally reconsidering for each case what precisely was traditionally in the legal habits, soon turned also to a more equitable interpretation, coherently adapting the law to the newer social instances. The law was then implemented with new evolutive Institutiones (legal concepts), while remaining in the traditional scheme. Praetors were replaced in 3rd century BC by a laical body of prudentes. Admission to this body was conditional upon proof of competence or experience.
Under the Roman Empire, schools of law were created, and the activity constantly became more academic. In the age from the early Roman Empire to the 3rd century, a relevant literature was produced by some notable groups including the Proculians and Sabinians. The scientific depth of the studies was unprecedented in ancient times.
After the 3rd century, Juris prudentia became a more bureaucratic activity, with few notable authors. It was during the Eastern Roman Empire (5th century) that legal studies were once again undertaken in depth, and it is from this cultural movement that Justinian's Corpus Juris Civilis was born.

Natural law

Natural law theory asserts that there are laws that are immanent in nature, to which enacted laws should correspond as closely as possible. This view is frequently summarised by the maxim an unjust law is not a true law, lex iniusta non est lex, in which 'unjust' is defined as contrary to natural law. Natural law is closely associated with morality and, in historically influential versions, with the intentions of God. To oversimplify its concepts somewhat, natural law theory attempts to identify a moral compass to guide the lawmaking power of the state and to promote 'the good'. Notions of an objective moral order, external to human legal systems, underlie natural law. What is right or wrong can vary according to the interests one is focused upon. Natural law is sometimes identified with the maxim that "an unjust law is no law at all", but as John Finnis, the most important of modern natural lawyers has argued, this maxim is a poor guide to the classical Thomist position.

Aristotle

Aristotle is often said to be the father of natural law.[7] Like his philosophical forefathers Socrates and Plato, Aristotle posited the existence of natural justice or natural right (dikaion physikon, δικαίον φυσικόν, Latin ius naturale). His association with natural law is largely due to the way in which he was interpreted by Thomas Aquinas.[8] This was based on Aquinas' conflation of natural law and natural right, the latter of which Aristotle posits in Book V of the Nicomachean Ethics (= Book IV of the Eudemian Ethics). Aquinas's influence was such as to affect a number of early translations of these passages,[9] though more recent translations render them more literally.[10]
Aristotle's theory of justice is bound up in his idea of the golden mean. Indeed his treatment of what he calls "political justice" derives from his discussion of "the just" as a moral virtue derived as the mean between opposing vices, just like every other virtue he describes.[11] His longest discussion of his theory of justice occurs in Nicomachean Ethics and begins by asking what sort of mean a just act is. He argues that the term "justice" actually refers to two different but related ideas: general justice and particular justice.[12][13] When a person's actions are completely virtuous in all matters in relation to others, Aristotle calls her "just" in the sense of "general justice;" as such this idea of justice is more or less coextensive with virtue.[14] "Particular" or "partial justice", by contrast, is the part of "general justice" or the individual virtue that is concerned with treating others equitably.[13] Aristotle moves from this unqualified discussion of justice to a qualified view of political justice, by which he means something close to the subject of modern jurisprudence. Of political justice, Aristotle argues that it is partly derived from nature and partly a matter of convention.[15] This can be taken as a statement that is similar to the views of modern natural law theorists. But it must also be remembered that Aristotle is describing a view of morality, not a system of law, and therefore his remarks as to nature are about the grounding of the morality enacted as law, not the laws themselves. The passage here is silent as to that question.
The best evidence of Aristotle's having thought there was a natural law comes from the Rhetoric, where Aristotle notes that, aside from the "particular" laws that each people has set up for itself, there is a "common" law that is according to nature.[16] The context of this remark, however, suggests only that Aristotle thought that it could be rhetorically advantageous to appeal to such a law, especially when the "particular" law of ones' own city was adverse to the case being made, not that there actually was such a law;[17] Aristotle, moreover, considered two of the three candidates for a universally valid, natural law suggested in this passage to be wrong.[18] Aristotle's theoretical paternity of the natural law tradition is consequently disputed.[citation needed]

Thomas Aquinas

Thomas Aquinas was the most important Western medieval legal scholar
Saint Thomas Aquinas [Thomas of Aquin, or Aquino] (c. 1225 – 7 March 1274) was a philosopher and theologian in the scholastic tradition, known as "Doctor Angelicus, Doctor Universalis". He is the foremost classical proponent of natural theology, and the father of the Thomistic school of philosophy, for a long time the primary philosophical approach of the Roman Catholic Church. The work for which he is best-known is the Summa Theologica. One of the thirty-three Doctors of the Church, he is considered by many Catholics to be the Church's greatest theologian. Consequently, many institutions of learning have been named after him.
Aquinas distinguished four kinds of law: eternal, natural, human and divine:
  • Eternal law refers to divine reason, known only to God. It is God's plan for the universe. Man needs this, for without it he would totally lack direction.
  • Natural law is the "participation" in the eternal law by rational human creatures, and is discovered by reason.
  • Divine law is revealed in the scriptures and is God's positive law for mankind.
  • Human law is supported by reason and enacted for the common good.[19]
Natural law, of course, is based on "first principles":
. . . this is the first precept of the law, that good is to be done and promoted, and evil is to be avoided. All other precepts of the natural law are based on this . . .[20]
The desires to live and to procreate are counted by Aquinas among those basic (natural) human values on which all other human values are based.

School of Salamanca

The School of Salamanca reformulated natural law, concluding that all humans are equal and have the same rights to life and liberty
Francisco de Vitoria was perhaps the first to develop a theory of ius gentium (the rights of peoples), and thus is an important figure in the transition to modernity. He extrapolated his ideas of legitimate sovereign power to society at the international level, concluding that this scope as well ought to be ruled by just forms respectable of the rights of all. The common good of the world is of a category superior to the good of each state. This meant that relations between states ought to pass from being justified by force to being justified by law and justice. Some scholars have upset the standard account of the origins of International law, which emphasises the seminal text De iure belli ac pacis by Grotius, and argued for Vitoria and, later, Suárez's importance as forerunners and, potentially, founders of the field.[21] Others, such as Koskenniemi, have argued that none of these humanist and scholastic thinkers can be understood to have founded international law in the modern sense, instead placing its origins in the post-1870 period.[22]
Francisco Suárez, regarded as among the greatest scholastics after Aquinas, subdivided the concept of ius gentium. Working with already well-formed categories, he carefully distinguished ius inter gentes from ius intra gentes. Ius inter gentes (which corresponds to modern international law) was something common to the majority of countries, although, being positive law, not natural law, was not necessarily universal. On the other hand, ius intra gentes, or civil law, is specific to each nation.

Thomas Hobbes

Thomas Hobbes was an English Enlightenment scholar
In his treatise Leviathan, (1651), Hobbes expresses a view of natural law as a precept, or general rule, found out by reason, by which a man is forbidden to do that which is destructive of his life, or takes away the means of preserving the same; and to omit that by which he thinks it may best be preserved. Hobbes was a social contractarian[23] and believed that the law gained peoples' tacit consent. He believed that society was formed from a state of nature to protect people from the state of war between mankind that exists otherwise. Life is, without an ordered society, "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short". It is commonly commented that Hobbes' views about the core of human nature were influenced by his times. The English Civil War and the Cromwellian dictatorship had taken place, and he felt absolute authority vested in a monarch, whose subjects obeyed the law, was the basis of a civilized society.

Lon Fuller

Writing after World War II, Lon L. Fuller notably emphasised that the law must meet certain formal requirements (such as being impartial and publicly knowable). To the extent that an institutional system of social control falls short of these requirements, Fuller argues, we are less inclined to recognise it as a system of law, or to give it our respect. Thus, law has an internal morality that goes beyond the social rules by which valid laws are made.

John Finnis

Sophisticated positivist and natural law theories sometimes resemble each other more than the above descriptions might suggest, and they may concede certain points to the other "side". Identifying a particular theorist as a positivist or a natural law theorist sometimes involves matters of emphasis and degree, and the particular influences on the theorist's work. In particular, the older natural lawyers, such as Aquinas and John Locke made no distinction between analytic and normative jurisprudence. But modern natural lawyers, such as John Finnis claim to be positivists, while still arguing that law is a basically moral creature.

Sharia and Fiqh in Islam

The first sura in a Qur'anic manuscript by Hattat Aziz Efendi.
Sharia (شَرِيعَةٌ) refers to the body of Islamic law. The term means "way" or "path"; it is the legal framework within which public and most private aspects of life are regulated for those living in a legal system based on Islamic principles of jurisprudence. Fiqh is the term for Islamic jurisprudence, made up of the rulings of Islamic jurists. A component of Islamic studies, Fiqh expounds the methodology by which Islamic law is derived from primary and secondary sources.
Mainstream Islam distinguishes fiqh, which means understanding the details and inferences drawn by scholars, from sharia, which refers to the principles behind the fiqh. Scholars hope that fiqh and sharia are in harmony in any given case, but this cannot be assured.[24]
Early forms of logic in Islamic philosophy were introduced in Islamic jurisprudence from the 7th century with the process of Qiyas. During the Islamic Golden Age, there was a logical debate among Islamic philosophers and jurists over whether the term Qiyas refers to analogical reasoning, inductive reasoning or categorical syllogism. Some Islamic scholars argued that Qiyas refers to reasoning. Ibn Hazm (994-1064) disagreed with this, arguing that Qiyas refers rather to categorical syllogism in a real sense and to analogical reasoning in a metaphorical sense. On the other hand, al-Ghazali (1058–1111) (and in modern times, Abu Muhammad Asem al-Maqdisi) argued that Qiyas refers to analogical reasoning in a real sense and categorical syllogism in a metaphorical sense. Other Islamic scholars at the time argued that the term Qiyas refers to both analogical reasoning and categorical syllogism in a real sense.[25]

Analytic jurisprudence

Hume made the famous is-ought distinction
Analytic, or 'clarificatory', jurisprudence means the use of a neutral point of view and descriptive language when referring to the aspects of legal systems. This was a philosophical development that rejected natural law's fusing of what law is and what it ought to be.[26] David Hume famously argued in A Treatise of Human Nature[27] that people invariably slip between describing that the world is a certain way to saying therefore we ought to conclude on a particular course of action. But as a matter of pure logic, one cannot conclude that we ought to do something merely because something is the case. So analysing and clarifying the way the world is must be treated as a strictly separate question to normative and evaluative ought questions.
The most important questions of analytic jurisprudence are: "What are laws?"; "What is the law?"; "What is the relationship between law and power/sociology?"; and "What is the relationship between law and morality?" Legal positivism is the dominant theory, although there are a growing number of critics, who offer their own interpretations.

Legal positivists

Positivism simply means that law is something that is "posited": laws are validly made in accordance with socially accepted rules. The positivist view on law can be seen to cover two broad principles: Firstly, that laws may seek to enforce justice, morality, or any other normative end, but their success or failure in doing so does not determine their validity. Provided a law is properly formed, in accordance with the rules recognized in the society concerned, it is a valid law, regardless of whether it is just by some other standard. Secondly, that law is nothing more than a set of rules to provide order and governance of society. No legal positivist, however, argues that it follows that the law is therefore to be obeyed, no matter what. This is seen as a separate question entirely.
  • What the law is (lex lata) - is determined by historical social practice (resulting in rules)
  • What the law ought to be (lex ferenda) - is determined by moral considerations.

Bentham and Austin

Bentham's utilitarian theories remained dominant in law until the twentieth century
One of the earliest legal positivists was Jeremy Bentham. Bentham was an early and staunch supporter of the utilitarian concept (along with Hume), an avid prison reformer, advocate for democracy, and strongly atheist. Bentham's views about law and jurisprudence were popularized by his student, John Austin. Austin was the first chair of law at the new University of London from 1829. Austin's utilitarian answer to "what is law?" was that law is "commands, backed by threat of sanctions, from a sovereign, to whom people have a habit of obedience".[28] Contemporary legal positivists have long abandoned this view, and have criticised its oversimplification, H. L. A. Hart particularly.

Hans Kelsen

Hans Kelsen is considered one of the preeminent jurists of the 20th century and has been highly influential in Europe and Latin America, although less so in common-law countries. His Pure Theory of Law aims to describe law as binding norms while at the same time refusing, itself, to evaluate those norms. That is, 'legal science' is to be separated from 'legal politics'. Central to the Pure Theory of Law is the notion of a 'basic norm (Grundnorm)'—a hypothetical norm, presupposed by the jurist, from which in a hierarchy all 'lower' norms in a legal system, beginning with constitutional law, are understood to derive their authority or 'bindingness'. In this way, Kelsen contends, the bindingness of legal norms, their specifically 'legal' character, can be understood without tracing it ultimately to some suprahuman source such as God, personified Nature or—of great importance in his time—a personified State or Nation.

H. L. A. Hart

In the Anglophone world, the pivotal writer was H. L. A. Hart, who argued that the law should be understood as a system of social rules. Hart rejected Kelsen's views that sanctions were essential to law and that a normative social phenomenon, like law, can not be grounded in non-normative social facts. Hart revived analytical jurisprudence as an important theoretical debate in the twentieth century through his book The Concept of Law.[29] As the professor of jurisprudence at Oxford University, Hart argued that law is a 'system of rules'.
Rules, said Hart, are divided into primary rules (rules of conduct) and secondary rules (rules addressed to officials to administer primary rules). Secondary rules are divided into rules of adjudication (to resolve legal disputes), rules of change (allowing laws to be varied) and the rule of recognition (allowing laws to be identified as valid). The "rule of recognition", a customary practice of the officials (especially judges) that identifies certain acts and decisions as sources of law. A pivotal book on Hart was written by Neil MacCormick[30] in 1981 (second edition due in 2007), which further refined and offered some important criticisms that led MacCormick to develop his own theory (the best example of which is his recently published Institutions of Law, 2007). Other important critiques have included that of Ronald Dworkin, John Finnis, and Joseph Raz.
In recent years, debates about the nature of law have become increasingly fine-grained. One important debate is within legal positivism. One school is sometimes called exclusive legal positivism, and it is associated with the view that the legal validity of a norm can never depend on its moral correctness. A second school is labeled inclusive legal positivism, a major proponent of which is Wil Waluchow, and it is associated with the view that moral considerations may determine the legal validity of a norm, but that it is not necessary that this is the case.

Joseph Raz

Some philosophers used to contend that positivism was the theory that there is "no necessary connection" between law and morality; but influential contemporary positivists, including Joseph Raz, John Gardner, and Leslie Green, reject that view. As Raz points out, it is a necessary truth that there are vices that a legal system cannot possibly have (for example, it cannot commit rape or murder).
Joseph Raz defends the positivist outlook, but criticised Hart's "soft social thesis" approach in The Authority of Law.[31] Raz argues that law is authority, identifiable purely through social sources, without reference to moral reasoning. Any categorisation of rules beyond their role as authority is better left to sociology than to jurisprudence.[32]

Ronald Dworkin

Ronald Dworkin sought a theory of law which would justify judges' ability to strike down democratically decided laws.
In his book Law's Empire[33] Dworkin attacked Hart and the positivists for their refusal to treat law as a moral issue. Dworkin argues that law is an 'interpretive' concept, that requires judges to find the best-fitting and most just solution to a legal dispute, given their constitutional traditions. According to him, law is not entirely based on social facts, but includes the morally best justification for the institutional facts and practices that we intuitively regard as legal. It follows on Dworkin's view that one cannot know whether a society has a legal system in force, or what any of its laws are, until one knows some moral truths about the justifications for the practices in that society. It is consistent with Dworkin's view—in contrast with the views of legal positivists or legal realists—that no-one in a society may know what its laws are, because no-one may know the best justification for its practices.
Interpretation, according to Dworkin's law as integrity theory, has two dimensions. To count as an interpretation, the reading of a text must meet the criterion of fit. Of those interpretations that fit, however, Dworkin maintains that the correct interpretation is the one that puts the political practices of the community in their best light, or makes of them the best that they can be. But many writers have doubted whether there is a single best justification for the complex practices of any given community, and others have doubted whether, even if there are, they should be counted as part of the law of that community.

Legal realism

Oliver Wendell Holmes was a self-styled legal realist
Legal realism was a view popular with some Scandinavian and American writers. Skeptical in tone, it held that the law should be understood and determined by the actual practices of courts, law offices, and police stations, rather than as the rules and doctrines set forth in statutes or learned treatises. It had some affinities with the sociology of law. The essential tenet of legal realism is that all law is made by human beings and, thus, is subject to human foibles, frailties and imperfections.
It has become quite common today to identify Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., as the main precursor of American Legal Realism (other influences include Roscoe Pound, Karl Llewellyn and Justice Benjamin Cardozo). Karl Llewellyn, another founder of the U.S. legal realism movement, similarly believed that the law is little more than putty in the hands of a judge who is able to shape the outcome of a case based on personal biases.[34] The chief inspiration for Scandinavian legal realism many consider to be the works of Axel Hägerström. Despite its decline in facial popularity, realism continues to influence a wide spectrum of jurisprudential schools today, including critical legal studies, feminist legal theory, critical race theory, sociology of law and law and economics.

Historical School

Historical jurisprudence came to prominence during the German debate over the proposed codification of German law. In his book On the Vocation of Our Age for Legislation and Jurisprudence,[35] Friedrich Carl von Savigny argued that Germany did not have a legal language that would support codification because the traditions, customs and beliefs of the German people did not include a belief in a code. The Historicists believe that the law originates with society.

Normative jurisprudence

In addition to the question, "What is law?", legal philosophy is also concerned with normative, or "evaluative" theories of law. What is the goal or purpose of law? What moral or political theories provide a foundation for the law? What is the proper function of law? What sorts of acts should be subject to punishment, and what sorts of punishment should be permitted? What is justice? What rights do we have? Is there a duty to obey the law? What value has the rule of law? Some of the different schools and leading thinkers are as follows.

Virtue jurisprudence

Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), a detail of The School of Athens
Aretaic moral theories such as contemporary virtue ethics emphasize the role of character in morality. Virtue jurisprudence is the view that the laws should promote the development of virtuous characters by citizens. Historically, this approach is associated mainly with Aristotle or Thomas Aquinas later. Contemporary virtue jurisprudence is inspired by philosophical work on virtue ethics.

Deontology

Kant was a pre-eminent Enlightenment thinker
Deontology is "the theory of duty or moral obligation."[36] The philosopher Immanuel Kant formulated one influential deontological theory of law. He argued that any rule we follow must be able to be universally applied, i.e. we must be willing for everyone to follow that rule. A contemporary deontological approach can be found in the work of the legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin.

Utilitarianism

Mill believed law should create happiness
Utilitarianism is the view that the laws should be crafted so as to produce the best consequences for the greatest number of people possible. Historically, utilitarian thinking about law is associated with the great philosopher, Jeremy Bentham. John Stuart Mill was a pupil of Bentham's and was the torch bearer for utilitarian philosophy through the late nineteenth century.[37] In contemporary legal theory, the utilitarian approach is frequently championed by scholars who work in the law and economics tradition. Also see Lysander Spooner.

John Rawls

John Rawls was an American philosopher, a professor of political philosophy at Harvard University and author of A Theory of Justice (1971), Political Liberalism, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, and The Law of Peoples. He is widely considered one of the most important English-language political philosophers of the 20th century. His theory of justice uses a device called the original position to ask us which principles of justice we would choose to regulate the basic institutions of our society if we were behind a 'veil of ignorance.' Imagine we do not know who we are - our race, sex, wealth status, class, or any distinguishing feature - so that we would not be biased in our own favour. Rawls argues from this 'original position' that we would choose exactly the same political liberties for everyone, like freedom of speech, the right to vote and so on. Also, we would choose a system where there is only inequality because that produces incentives enough for the economic well-being of all society, especially the poorest. This is Rawls's famous 'difference principle'. Justice is fairness, in the sense that the fairness of the original position of choice guarantees the fairness of the principles chosen in that position.
There are many other normative approaches to the philosophy of law, including critical legal studies and libertarian theories of law.